top of page
Writer's pictureSaga Foss

The Socratic Conundrum and Socratic Thinking

Knowing nothing himself, Socrates was able to effectively challenge others' claims about their own knowledge. In order to make his students feel awkward and eventually acknowledge they did not know anything, he would ask them questions about topics in which they were meant to be experts.


Socrates was well known for his incessant curiosity to learn the secrets of others. He went all throughout Athens, interviewing politicians, poets, craftsmen, and other experts in their fields.


In his quest to disprove the Oracle, Socrates learned that many of the people who claimed to know everything did not. Poets could move people without understanding their meaning; craftspeople had abilities but no real comprehension of the world; and politicians professed wisdom without grasping philosophy or ethics.


Socrates was a guy who recognized that his intellect alone could not serve as a basis for virtue and that he needed to work on being truly smart. This was a brand-new way of life that would finally give him the independence to direct his energies toward doing what was right.


The intriguing conundrum known as the Socratic Paradox has baffled philosophers for ages. The gist of it is that knowing what you want to know and asking questions about it are mutually exclusive.


As a philosophical strategy, the Socratic method is an admirable attempt to resolve this impasse. The procedure is based on a cycle of asking and answering numerous questions. The Socratic approach works very well when trying to solve the challenge of responding to non-empirical issues, such as those pertaining to metaphysics.


Changing your perspective is the most effective strategy for solving this puzzle. Answering "What is knowledge?" is central to the Socratic approach. This may seem like a boring question, but it's actually rather crucial because it sets the stage for everything else in a person's life. To do this, one must examine their own humanity and grow from their experiences.


No one intentionally acts wrong, according to Socrates. All of a person's voluntary actions, however, are done with the intention of doing good (Gorgias 467c–468b).


Philosophers who subscribe to Socratic ethics have maintained that sentiments like these should be passed down from generation to generation as aphorisms. This is due to the fact that they effectively summarize Socratic ethics and are simple to internalize.


The interpretation of the Socratic paradoxes, however, is very contentious. For instance, whether or not Socrates agrees with "the many's" hedonistic interpretation of akrasia is a point of contention.


Judith Weiss examines the numerous interpretations that Socrates could have made of this crucial line in her book Socrates and the Socratic Paradox: I Know That I Know Nothing. Her methodology is novel, and her interpretation will likely provoke more discussion among experts.


Socrates attempts to explain virtue after being challenged by Meno on the topic. Typical of Platonic epistemology is Socrates' quest for a better definition.


In order for Socrates' attempt to describe virtue to be fruitful, it must reveal the very nature of virtue itself, not just what it is or what good people do.


According to Roslyn Weiss's book, The Socratic Paradox and Its Enemies, the philosopher used paradoxes not to advance some nebulous aim but to undermine his opponents' arguments. According to Weiss, the Socratic paradoxes were Socrates' technique of refuting esoteric beliefs like the denial of akrasia and the contention that no one knowingly engages in wrongdoing.


Weiss also defines "epithumein" and "boulesthai," two concepts used by Socrates. The latter designates an intellectual yearning, while the former denotes an animalistic hunger.

3 views0 comments

Comments


bottom of page